An Unpopular Reading of the Communist Manifesto (1848)
Introduction
The Communist Manifesto (1848; hereafter CM) is probably Marx’s most famous, yet misunderstood, work. It has consistently been both a basis for leftwing strategy and an object of rightwing critique. But common invocations of the text often extend no further than a repetition of some platitudes contained in the first and last paragraphs. For many others, it is often the only one of Marx’s works that they will ever read. This is unfortunate, because the CM is far from Marx’s most developed work nor does it contain his most important insights on the inner workings of capitalism. Still, on a close read, and with some knowledge of Marx’s broader thought, it is possible to glean some kernels of Marx’s key ideas in their embryonic stages. Thus, in this essay, I indicate some of these kernels, elaborate on their meaning, and use them to clarify some of the most common misunderstandings vis-a-vis the CM and communism in general.
Overview of the Communist Manifesto
In section three, “Socialist and Communist Literature,” M&E critique prior scholarship on Socialism and Communism. This relates to the first two sections because M&E advocate a stage-theory of historical development, a part of historical materialism, in which societies move through definite stages from feudalism, to capitalism, and then to socialism. And, importantly, within this process, it is the working class that is the revolutionary agent that will carry the transition from capitalism to socialism. Based on this, there are four main targets of M&E’s critique in the third section. First, they criticize the idea of “reactionary socialism” where the aristocracy tried to appeal directly to the working class against the emergent bourgeoisie. This was a backwards and reactionary movement, say M&E, because the working class and bourgeoisie must develop together against the aristocracy. Second, they critique the idea of “True Socialism” in Germany which was when some German elites and academics tried to apply the ideas of the French Revolution to their newly-emerging state. The problem? Germany still wasn’t a bourgeois democracy! Thus the German critics were actually hindering the movement by attacking liberalism before it had been achieved. Third, M&E critique the idea of “bourgeois socialism” or, essentially, socialism for the rich. Here, they argue that the working class must be front and center of the revolutionary movement, and that this is also a concrete political rather than just an abstract elite struggle. Fourth, they attack notions of “utopian socialism.” The basis for this critique is basically that utopian socialist movements put the cart before the horse. That is to say, their vision of a harmonious future society of abundance is predicated on a level of advancement of the means of production which has not yet been achieved. Thus, they presuppose the very thing that they are proposing to change! As such, theirs is an impossibility and should not be the basis for revolutionary strategy. However, M&E do positively appraise utopian socialism as an example of proletarian yearning for an alternative society outside of capitalism.
The CM closes with a fourth section on communists position vis-a-vis various existing national political struggles. But more on this later.
Common misconceptions
Hard-won, self-acquired, self-earned property! Do you mean the property of the petty artisan and of the small peasant, a form of property that preceded the bourgeois form? There is no need to abolish that; the development of industry has to a great extent already destroyed it, and is still destroying it daily (235).And again:
You are horrified at our intending to do away with private property. But in your existing society, private property is already done away with for nine-tenths of the population; its existence for the few is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of those nine-tenths. You reproach us, therefore, with intending to do away with a form of property the necessary condition for whose existence is the non-existence of any property for the immense majority of society (237).Thus, M&E not only distinguish between property and bourgeois property, but they also note that workers already don’t own anything anyway. Thus, how can communists be in favor of abolishing something that doesn’t exist! No, communists do not seek to take from the working class what they don’t have, but rather simply to return to them what is rightfully theirs. Again, M&E:
We by no means intend to abolish this personal appropriation of the products of labour [...]. All that we want to do away with is the miserable character of this appropriation, under which the labourer lives merely to increase capital, and is allowed to live only in so far as the interest of the ruling class requires it (236).There is another truism that in fact thus captures the spirit of communism much better, the idea of “wage slavery” and the abolishment of this. Many misunderstandings could be easily cleared up, therefore, if more people understood private property simply as wage slavery.
The second common misconception, connecting to private property, regards the idea of freedom. Freedom has a negative image among leftists today since they regard it simply as a rallying call of the libertarian right. However, this is unfortunate, since all these leftists see is the same caricature of freedom that has underpinned liberalism throughout its history, and which was a main target of Marx’s critique. Consequently, many on the authoritarian left have been led to completely abandon notions of individual freedom altogether in place of abstract notions of “society.” Yet this is a complete chimera, and a mistake of the worst order. The entire thrust of Marx’s whole project was oriented toward the liberation of the individual as a prerequisite for their rejoining with society, i.e., the completion of social man or species being (Gattungswesen). The CM is very clear about the precise notion of freedom that they are critiquing: “by freedom is meant, under the present bourgeois conditions of production, free trade, free selling and buying” (237). So, in other words, they oppose what can simply be termed bourgeois freedom, but certainly not freedom in general. In particular, they attack the narrow bourgeois interpretation of “freedom” as simply the “freedom” to buy and sell labor power. In their view, this is the precise opposite of true freedom; it is a form of slavery.
The third misconception regards the notion of “family.” This is where the importance of the base-superstructure relationship especially comes into play. Many on the left and even proclaimed Marxists since Marx’s time have called for the abolition of the family or of so-called patriarchal relationships etc. But what they often fail to realize is that M&E were not criticizing the family per se, but rather only the bourgeois notion of family. Starting to see a pattern here? Just like private property, freedom, etc., all of these are qualified in M&E’s lexicon with the phrase “bourgeois” (read capitalist). This is because a basic tenet of historical materialism holds that the underlying social and economic relations influences the form of everything else, politics, culture, institutions, you name it. Put differently, how people think and act, what they believe, etc. totally changes based on their relationship to the means of their own reproduction, i.e. their class. In the CM, M&E explicitly do not call for the abolition of the family; they only call for the end to bourgeois notions of the family. In fact, quite the opposite, they even lament how capitalism has already destroyed familial bonds for most of the working class.
On what foundation is the present family, the bourgeois family, based? On capital, on private gain. In its completely developed form this family exists only among the bourgeoisie. But this state of things finds its complement in the practical absence of the family among the proletarians [...] (239).In other words, bourgeois society reduces all relationships, even familial ones, to merely a monetary relationship of convenience. The mediating agent between man and man, in other words, is money. Moreover, capitalism strips the working class of their very families altogether! By subjecting them to waged labor, it forces man, woman, and child to act as independent, isolated individuals, and scatters them from the home and onto the factory, cash register, or cubicle.
So, what M&E really want to abolish is this exploitative, wage relationship which underlies the entire bourgeois (capitalist) mode of production. “Do you charge us with wanting to stop the exploitation of children by their parents?,” they ask, “To this crime we plead guilty” (239). Here, M&E are specifically referring to working class families in their day and age who were so poor that they had to send even their children to work in factories. But this is a reflection not of so-called “patriarchal relations.” Instead, it is a totally new phenomenon and reflection of the dominant bourgeois mode of production, the exploitative wage relationship. As M&E explain,
The bourgeois clap-trap about the family and education, about the hallowed co-relation of parent and child, becomes all the more disgusting, the more, by the action of Modern Industry, all family ties among the proletarians are torn asunder, and their children transformed into simple articles of commerce and instruments of labor (240).It is not communists therefore that want to abolish the family, but capitalism itself which already does this.
The working men have no country. We cannot take from them what they have not got. Since the proletariat must first of all acquire political supremacy, must rise to be the leading class of the nation, must constitute itself the nation, it is, so far, itself national, though not in the bourgeois sense of the word (241).See how this works? It’s exactly like all the other notions examined thus far. It’s not the notion itself that M&E criticize but only its bourgeois form. And underlying this, again, is the unequal wage relationship, the key thing that M&E want to transform.
The fifth and last point that is frequently misunderstood relates to communism itself. Most people probably think that communism means dressing like Che Guevara, living in hippy communes, and making complicated academic arguments. But communism is actually none of these things. Communism isn’t even about fighting the patriarchy or achieving equal liberal rights for everyone. Neither is it about going on strikes and getting wage raises. Rather, the CM spells out very clearly that communism is simply the reflection of the immediate demands of the working class. That’s it. Communists, say M&E, “have no interests separate and apart from those of the proletariat as a whole. They do not set up any sectarian principles of their own, by which to shape and mould the proletarian movement” (234). Now, this is quite astounding. It makes one wonder whether many professed leftists have ever actually even read this key work that they claim forms the basis for their strategy. Instead, one is more likely today to find “leftists,” usually in bourgeois positions of power such as academia, berating the working class for their so-called “backwards” social customs and “ignorance.”
But there is one difference, note M&E. Communists support the working class everywhere at all times in all their various struggles. But they do so with the long game in mind. They know that the end goal itself, after they have helped the working class achieve political power, is none other than the abolition of wage labor itself, the prohibition of the buying and selling of labor power. That will spell not only the end of nation-states, the entire unequal global division of labor, and other exploitative reflections of bourgeois culture, but also of capitalism itself. Now, this should already be apparent from the CM’s previous critique of bourgeois property and cultural institutions thus far. But just so there is no confusion, it should also be noted that this is one of the only precise policy recommendations that Marx makes in his magnum opus, Capital. There, at the end of Chapter Ten, Volume One, he proposes that workers pass a law prohibiting the buying and selling of labor power, and explicitly states that this would spell the end of capitalism.
Conclusion
Each of these points regarding the nature of capitalism and communism, as I showed, are frequently misunderstood. Although it helps to read the rest of Marx’s works to understand why this is the case, as I explained, it is still possible to grasp Marx’s basic ideas re these points even just with the CM. I would suggest therefore that people do read the CM and study it carefully, since it contains these important, condensed kernels of Marx’s thought. However, aside from the fact that even its main ideas are often misunderstood, I also don’t think the CM forms the best basis for revolutionary strategy. For this, one would have to turn to the rest of Marx’s later works, especially Capital as well as subsequent Marxist theory. And, lastly, I would encourage the contemporary left not to abandon or to berate the working class and their demands, even if they sometimes seem offensive, since in doing so, they in fact are acting as the reactionary counterforce against our time’s sole revolutionary agent.